# Table of Contents - [`[2016-07-30]` Conway games](#mthwrldwlfrmcmcnwygmhtmlcnwygms) - [= ({0}, {0}) = {0|0}](#527_2073) - [related](#rltd) [[math]] # `[2016-07-30]` [Conway games](http://mathworld.wolfram.com/ConwayGame.html) 1. L, R : sets of games, then G = is a game 2. DGC: no infinite sequence of games Gi = i, Ri> with G(i+1) ∈ Li ∪ Ri for all i ∈ N L and R are left and right options of G. G = {L1, L2, … Ln | R1, R2 … Rm } 0 = ({} , {}) = {|} 1 = ({0}, {}} = {0|} -1 = ({} , {0}) = {|0} # = ({0}, {0}) = {0|0} n = {n - 1|} 1/2 = {0|1} Conway induction: ICGN. 0 satisfies automatically. Proof: infinite sequence of games not satisfying the property, contradiciton. Conway induction implies DGC Finitely many positions: short Same moves: impartial game Abelian group: 1. 0 = {|} 2. G + H = {(GL + H) ∪ (G + HL | (GR + H) ∪ (G + HR)} 3. -G = {-GR | -GL} The set of all Conway games forms a partial order with respect to the comparison operations: 1. G=H. If the second player to move in the game G-H can win (G and H are equal). 2. G||H. If the first player to move in the game G-H can win (G and H are fuzzy). 3. G>H. If Left can win the game G-H whether he plays first or not (G is greater than H). 4. G1,L2,…}|GR} and L2>=L1, then G={{L2,…}|GR}; and if G={GL|{R1,R\_ 2,…}} and R1>=R2, then G={GL|{R2,…}}. 1. Replacement of reversible moves: if G={{{AL|{A(R1),A(R2),…}},G(L2),…}|GR}, and A(R1)<=G, then G={{{A^ (R1L)},G(L2),…}|GR}. G is said to be in canonical form if it has no dominated options or reversible moves. If G and H are both in canonical form, they both have the same sets of left and right options and so are equal. # related [[math]]